Friday, February 28, 2014

Co-founder of defunct Chicago escrow company indicted on federal fraud charges

Editor's note:  FEDs: Double check to see if this guy had any doings with the Probate Court of Cook County.  Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster, ProbateSharks.com



Editor's note update 3-1-2014: Evidently,  Your ProbateShark must have struck a nerve about this guy and the Probate Court due to the upswing in views for this posting.  Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster, ProbateSharks.com


Editor's note update 3-1-2014: This Shark wonders what banks service these fraudulent escrow accounts? Maybe one of the banks that cashed Alice R. Gore's forged annuity checks? Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster, ProbateSharks.com


Editor's note update 3-8-2014: Your ProbateShark believes this Lurie is a miscreant's miscreant. He is now in the top ten of ProbateSharks.com volume leaders and is approaching the coveted #5 position. This Shark believes this volume leader is deeply involved in all kinds of fraud.  Is he related to someone influential? Why the massive interest? Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster, ProbateSharks.com

Editor's note update 3-9-2014:   This post approaches #4 all-time ProbateSharks.com volume record.  Can someone comment to this Shark why Lurie is so important to our readers? We know he is a crook...but look at all the other crooks in the Cook County Probate Court memorialized in this blog.  Why?  Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster,  ProbateSharks.com


Related links:
http://highlandpark.patch.com/groups/police-and-fire/p/highland-park-man-charged-with-battery


http://newssun.suntimes.com/news/25870130-418/former-head-of-escrow-company-facing-federal-fraud-charges.html


http://www.loansafe.org/executive-charged-with-misusing-funds



http://www3.illinois.gov/PressReleases/ShowPressRelease.cfm?SubjectID=2&RecNum=8030



http://articles.chicagotribune.com/2009-03-27/news/0903260694_1_escrow-accounts-probing-Illinois



http://www.justice.gov/usao/iln/pr/chicago/2014/pr0227_01.html

 

Co-founder of defunct Chicago escrow company indicted on federal fraud charges


  • print
  • Email
    Share
    5


    LinkedIn
    0




The co-founder of a defunct Chicago escrow company was indicted on federal fraud charges on Wednesday for allegedly engaging in a Ponzi-like scheme and using more than $500,000 of customer funds for personal expenses and to operate other businesses.
Derek Lurie, was charged with five counts of mail fraud. Each count carries a maximum penalty of 20 years in prison and a $250,000 fine.
Lurie’s company, American Escrow, which had offices on West Randolph and North May streets, went out of business in 2009. The company didn’t issue refunds and left some of its customers with delinquent tax and insurance bills.
 
“This is a very stale investigation and a wrong-headed indictment. This is not a criminal case,” said Thomas Durkin, an attorney representing American Escrow.
The indictment alleges Lurie used some of the money it collected from customers to cover personal expenses, such as car payments and the costs of renovating a condominium in Miami.
American Escrow, which operated at a “significant deficit,” survived by juggling new escrow funds to pay off tax and insurance payments due at different times throughout the year, according to the indictment.
Lurie, 40, is due in court on March 11 for his arraignment.
Earlier this month, Jacqueline Cruz, a former American Escrow employee, was indicted for allegedly fraudulently obtaining more than $400,000 from the company.
Cruz, who oversaw the payment of customers’ property taxes and private mortgage insurance, wrote 122 company checks to herself between May 2005 and March 2009, according to her indictment.
Cruz, 38, is now living in Okinawa, Japan. She pleaded not guilty on Feb. 19 to three counts of mail fraud.
acancino@tribune.com

Eric Holder Goes To Extraordinary Lengths To Prove Obamacare’s Viabilty

  • 27 Feb 2014 at 1:37 PM
  • Department of Justice, Eric Holder, Health Care / Medicine
  • Eric Holder Goes To Extraordinary Lengths To Prove Obamacare’s Viabilty


    Attorney General Eric Holder was hospitalized today after experiencing faintness and shortness of breath, as noted by the ABA Journal. According to Justice Department spokesman Brian Fallon, Holder was taken to the hospital as a precaution, after experiencing symptoms during a morning staff meeting.
    When reached for comment, Holder said, “Please God, let me use my Covington & Burling health care. Don’t send me to a death panel.”
    Just kidding. Holder is fine (I hope, or else this post is going to look like very poor taste). Let’s wish him the best for a speedy recovery. Those drones can’t figure out whom to strike by themselves.
    Attorney General Holder Is hospitalized [ABA Journal]

    How do we choose proper performance measures for prisons?

    How do we choose proper performance measures for prisons?

    This is the fourth post in a series about my new article, Prison Accountability and Performance Measures, which is in the current issue of the Emory Law Journal. In Monday’s post, I introduced the issue and advocated greater use of performance measures, which I’ll come back to later this week. In Tuesday’s post, I discussed why we don’t know much about the comparative cost or quality of public vs. private prisons. In Wednesday’s post, I talked about why introducing performance measures would be a good idea.
    Today, I’ll discuss some of the normative issues involved in what measures to choose. I’ll also start on some potential concerns about, and critiques of, implementing performance measures — a discussion I’ll finish up tomorrow.
    *     *     *
    What Measures to Choose
    Click here to subscribe.
    Click here to subscribe.
    The earlier discussion of how to define recidivism shows that a lot rides on choosing the outcome measures judiciously. This applies across the board, not just to recidivism. This section considers two distinct aspects of performance measures. The first is that wherever outcome measures have been used, output measures haven’t been abandoned. The second is that what outcomes to measure—and even whether something counts as an output or outcome measure—is inevitably a value-laden question, which must be resolved for a performance-based compensation scheme to go forward. The inevitable incompleteness of outcome measures—and therefore the need to supplement outcomes with outputs—can give rise to undesirable strategic behavior, which I discuss in a later section.
    Adopting specific outcomes to measure is equivalent to adopting what John DiIulio calls an “operational” goal—“an image of a desired future state of affairs that can be compared unambiguously to an actual or existing state of affairs.” “‘Improving the quality of public education in America’ is a nonoperational goal; ‘Increasing the average verbal and math SAT scores of public school students by 20% between the year 1992 and the year 2000’ is an operational goal.” Similarly, “[r]eforming criminals” is nonoperational, while “[d]oubling the rate of inmate participation in prison industry programs” is operational. That last goal was output-based, but there’s no reason we can’t, as in the education example, adopt an outcome-based goal—we could just agree on a convenient if arbitrary measure of how well criminals are reformed, such as the two-year reconviction rate. Moreover, there’s no reason to adopt a numerical target as the goal (which would be binary); the goal might merely be (thinking more continuously) to reduce the rate as far as possible. And there’s no reason to adopt a unique goal: multiple operational goals can be implemented in one part of an overall index that determines compensation.
    A useful way to explore this question is to examine some existing prison performance measures. Perhaps one of the oldest formal approaches to measuring prison performance is the Correctional Institutions Environment Scale developed by Rudolph Moos in the late 1960s and often used in the 1970s. The Moos scale contains several subscales: “Involvement,” “Support,” “Expressiveness,” “Autonomy,” “Practical Orientation,” “Personal Problem Orientation,” “Order and Organization,” “Clarity,” and “Staff Control.” These elements generally aren’t true performance measures, and it’s immediately apparent from their definitions that some are highly impressionistic. The “Involvement” variable “[m]easures how active and energetic residents are”; the “Support” variable “[m]easures the extent to which residents are encouraged to be helpful and supportive”; and so on, with an emphasis on measuring the extent of supportiveness and encouragement. The scale was criticized because it wasn’t clear what the difference between some of the elements was and to what extent they were correlated, and even to what extent they described a real phenomenon. Some critics wrote that “when the CIES is administered and the individual scores are tallied and averaged, we really have no idea what the scores on the nine subscales indicate.” Ultimately, the scale was “determined not to possess acceptable validity.”
    A later approach, described in 1980 in a report by Martha Burt, uses five types of measures: “Measures of Security,” including the escape rate and escape seriousness; “Measures of Living and Safety Conditions,” such as victimization, overcrowding, and sanitation; “Measures of Inmate Health” (both physical and mental); “Intermediate Products of Programs and Services” like improvements in basic skills and vocational education completed; and “Measures of Post-Release Success,” including employment success and recidivism. Only the fourth category is explicitly labeled “Intermediate Products,” but some of the other measures are also outputs, not outcomes—see, for instance, the use of hospitalizations and sick days in the measures of inmate health.
    The mixing of output and outcome measures is fairly typical; John DiIulio criticizes the BOP’s Key Indicators/Strategic Support System for also “indiscriminate[ly] mixing . . . process [i.e., input or output] and performance [i.e., outcome] measures.” But DiIulio himself has measured prison quality in terms of “order (rates of individual and collective violence and other forms of misconduct), amenity (availability of clean cells, decent food, etc.), and service (availability of work opportunities, educational programs, etc.)”: note the output measures in the inclusion of the availability (not the effectiveness) of programming.
    The MTC Institute, the research arm of the private prison firm Management & Training Corp. (MTC), likewise calls for holding prisons accountable for “outcomes”; but these “outcomes” include not only assaults, escapes, recidivism, overcrowding, and the like, but also outputs like “[s]ubstance abuse education/treatment completions” and “[p]roportion of inmates participating in spiritual development program(s).”
    The American Correctional Association’s performance-based standards for correctional health care raise the same issue. Some of these are true outcomes, like “the rate of positive tuberculin skin tests” or the suicide rate, though others are process measures or expected practices, like whether an offender “is informed about access to health systems and the grievance procedure.” The Prison Social Climate Survey, which is based on inmate and staff surveys, likewise mixes outcomes (such as crowding or safety) with outputs (such as whether the prison is a pleasant place to work for staff).
    It is clear, then, that outcomes and output measures tend to go together; no doubt this is because not all outcomes are well measurable. Moreover, the choice of measures, and even the basic question of whether to classify a measure as an output or an outcome, is inevitably value-laden. We can see this clearly by examining Charles Logan’s “quality of confinement” index, one of the more highly regarded prison performance measures. Logan’s performance indicators focus on eight broad categories:
    1. “Security (‘keep them in’).”
    2. “Safety (‘keep them safe’).”
    3. “Order (‘keep them in line’).”
    4. “Care (‘keep them healthy’).”
    5. “Activity (‘keep them busy’).”
    6. “Justice (‘do it with fairness’).”
    7. “Conditions (‘without undue suffering’).”
    8. “Management (‘as efficiently as possible’).”
    Each of these categories contains a number of subdimensions: for instance, the “security” category contains the subdimensions of security procedures, drug use, significant incidents, community exposure, freedom of movement, and staffing adequacy. The “safety” category contains safety of inmates, safety of staff, dangerousness of inmates, safety of environment, and (again) staffing adequacy.
    And, finally, Logan decomposes these subdimensions into specific numerical measures: number of escapes, proportion of staff who have observed staff ignoring inmate misconduct, ratio of resident population to security staff, drug-related incidents, and so on. In all—over all eight dimensions—there are a few hundred measures. Logan used this index to evaluate three women’s prisons in New Mexico and West Virginia.
    None of Logan’s measures involve how many inmates get rehabilitated. But this is also intentional. First, actual rehabilitation is out of the direct control of prisons. Logan has a preference for measuring things that are within prisons’ “direct sphere of influence”; what we measure “ought to be achievable and measurable mostly within the prison itself.” Second, including rehabilitation endorses the rehabilitative model of criminal punishment, and Logan makes it clear that his model is retributive, not rehabilitative. Prisons, in his view, shouldn’t “add to (any more than . . . avoid or . . . compensate for) the pain and suffering inherent in being forcibly separated from civil society[;] . . . coercive confinement carries with it an obligation to meet the basic needs of prisoners at a reasonable standard of decency.”
    Logan’s concern for focusing on what a prison can control and focusing on the retributive goal merge in the following statement: “a prison does not have to justify itself as a tool of rehabilitation or crime control or any other instrumental purpose at which an army of critics will forever claim it to be a failure.” (Of course “[i]t would be very nice if the prison programs [counted in the ‘activity’ dimension] had rehabilitative effects,” and perhaps they do, but whether they do or don’t doesn’t enter into the index.)
    Fair enough. What this illustrates is that you can’t judge particular measures to be desirable unless you have a normative theory that proclaims certain goals to be desirable, and such a political discussion is necessary before one can commit oneself to a particular form of performance measures. “[W]ithout declared goals, we cannot hold a jurisdiction accountable, and performance measurement is meaningless.”
    This normative issue arises wherever performance measurements are used. John DiIulio describes how John Chubb and Terry Moe “measure school performance strictly in terms of pupils’ achievements on a battery of standardized tests, accepting the schools’ value as instruments of socialization and civics training as important but secondary.” On the relative value of test scores vs. socialization, your mileage may vary.
    Likewise, for the correctional system, there is a great variety of available goals; prisons should punish, rehabilitate, deter, incapacitate, and reintegrate—all, says John DiIulio, “without violating the public conscience (humane treatment), jeopardizing the public law (constitutional rights), emptying the public purse (cost containment), or weakening the tradition of State and local public administration (federalism).” So we need to have a political discussion about what the appropriate goals are.
    One’s normative theory also affects whether a particular measure is an output or an outcome; this classification, which I’ve been using casually so far as if it were value-neutral, is in fact anything but. If we didn’t care about inmates but only cared about the outside world, perhaps only recidivism would be relevant. The quality of living conditions or inmate literacy would merely be outputs, which we would care about only to the extent that they affected recidivism; they wouldn’t need to independently enter the compensation function as long as we already counted recidivism. But we might independently care about inmates’ living conditions for many reasons; if we do, living conditions become an actual outcome of the system.
    Thus, some of Logan’s dimensions, like “activity,” which I’m inclined to call an output measure, might be an outcome measure given Logan’s normative perspective. The same goes for variables like prison employees’ job satisfaction (which I consider an output measure because it’s only instrumentally relevant to prison quality, but which others who care about labor conditions might treat differently) or whether inmates have difficulty concentrating (which—unlike, say, overcrowding or physical safety—many may not consider an appropriate dimension for prison evaluation).
    Some of the measures, though, for instance the number of urinalysis tests conducted based on suspicion, are output measures under any definition, and these have the problem that it’s ambiguous whether they’re good or bad. Do we want more or fewer urinalysis tests based on suspicion? More tests could mean that drug use has gone up; or it could mean that prison authorities are getting more serious about controlling drug use. Even worse, prison authorities’ stringency is something prison authorities themselves can control; this is a serious problem, which I discuss below.
    As a final note, I’ll mention that while it’s vitally important to have good cost measures that are adequate for comparing public and private prisons, it’s not necessary to include cost in the private contractor’s compensation. If we couldn’t measure quality, perhaps there would be a role for rate-of-return regulation, which might at least limit some of the private sector’s harmful cost-cutting tendencies. But if we’re going to engage in quality measurement, we might as well enforce quality directly by getting the rewards or penalties “right”; let the private firms worry about their own costs.
    *     *     *
    Concerns and Critiques
    Despite the advantages discussed in the previous section, the use of performance measures has its pitfalls.
    One concern, so obvious as not to merit its own section heading, is the issue of administrative costs. Recidivism-based contracts require one to track released prisoners adequately. Perhaps there would be substantial startup costs—though current probation and parole systems already track releases and monitor employment, recidivism, and other relevant outcomes, so at least some of these costs are already sunk. Moreover, if performance-based contracting is beneficial at all, its benefits are probably great enough that these startup costs are worthwhile.
    This Part focuses on other concerns and critiques. First, there is the concern that one can’t set the proper prices in a theoretically defensible way. Second, there’s the concern that performance-based compensation will affect market structure, either by driving out the public-interested or by driving out the risk-averse. Third — I’m saving this for tomorrow’s post — there’s the concern that performance-based compensation will lead to undesirable strategic behavior, for instance via manipulation of the choice of performance goals, by distorting effort across various dimensions of performance, by distorting effort across various types of inmate, and by encouraging outright falsification.
    What Prices to Set
    The focus on performance measures might seem grating to those who criticize the turn toward efficiency analysis and comparative effectiveness and stress moral considerations. But one can support performance measures without endorsing efficiency in any way—in fact, as a better way of achieving particular moral goals.
    I myself have been critical of a focus on efficiency in the context of regulatory cost–benefit analysis, another example of hard-numbers-based accountability. To restate the problems of cost–benefit analysis in the prison context: What’s the social value of having less recidivism? To ask this in an economic context, we’d have to know either the maximum amount people would be willing to pay to reduce crime, or the minimum amount people would accept to acquiesce in an increase in crime. These are in general different amounts, and the choice between them is value-laden. Suppose we choose one of these numbers to measure; we may find that, when surveyed, some people—who reject the very notion of paying or being paid for reductions or increases in crime—give answers of zero or infinity for their willingness to pay or accept; the number we’re seeking may just not exist for these people. Some people may have true willingness to pay or accept, but they don’t even know what these numbers are: we only come to know such numbers because of our experience paying for and consuming goods and services in the real world, but increases and decreases in crime generally aren’t traded in markets. So the very act of asking for the number may bring some number into being, but there’s no reason to suppose it’s accurate. Or, people may know the number, but there’s no incentive for them to truthfully reveal it in surveys.
    Even if we use non-survey-based estimation methods—How much higher are house prices in lower-crime areas? How much do people pay to avoid crime?—econometric analysis isn’t good enough to give us the correct number. The political process is also likely to manipulate the numbers. Moreover, concerns that are hard to quantify can be systematically slighted.
    In short, “[w]hile cost–benefit analysis may look like rationality, perhaps it’s merely rationalism.” And these are just the problems for people who accept the utilitarian basis of cost–benefit analysis. The problems for those who reject utilitarianism as a moral philosophy are even greater. Surely corrections policy, of all things, should be decided with respect to morality and human values rather than numbers?
    These are real problems with cost–benefit analysis, and they potentially infect performance-based contracting as well. Setting the incentives in a performance-based contract means either setting the relative weights of every component of performance, or (equivalently) setting the separate rewards or penalties for every component of performance. Getting the prices “right,” in an efficiency sense, requires knowing the social value of the different components of performance; if that social value doesn’t exist or can’t be measured, it’s an impossible task.
    I agree and disagree with this critique.
    As to the moral objection, even though moral values have an extremely important place in criminal law and policy, I have no essential problem with using economic incentives to improve outcomes in the process. I’ve argued elsewhere that the valid arguments for or against private prisons generally are essentially empirical; measuring performance is an essential part of that debate, even though the choice of outcomes to measure is a value-laden enterprise; and attaching incentives to those performance measures is eminently justifiable if the result is a morally more just correctional system.
    As to the theoretical incoherence objection, I’m sympathetic. But the enterprise can still be salvaged if we adopt a humble attitude. Rather than trying to achieve incentives that are correct in some abstract sense, we can just try to muddle through and ameliorate the problems of the current system by attaching some weight to factors that traditionally haven’t been rewarded. None of this requires buying into the efficiency norm. Maybe the weights will be wrong, but “[t]he basic question . . . is whether the dangers of providing improper incentives through imperfect models outweigh the benefits of providing program direction and accountability.” Is adding this element of imperfect, numbers-based accountability better than not? The remaining sections in this Part address this question.
    Effects on Market Structure
    This section discusses how performance-based compensation can change the composition of providers. First, it will attract providers who respond better to market incentives, which might affect the overall public-interestedness of the industry. Second, because performance-based compensation is riskier than flat-rate compensation, it will discourage the more risk-averse providers.
    1. Public-Interestedness
    Todd Henderson and Fred Tung address this concern in the context of performance-based compensation for regulators. If regulators are currently public-interested, introducing market incentives might change the culture within the agency. “Once diligence has been priced, perhaps some regulators will slack.”
    This form of compensation will also affect the mix of people who choose to be regulators. “Public service motives might be displaced by financial motivations among new hires . . . . Eventually, the composition of the regulatory agency could change for the worse.”
    Henderson and Tung conclude, citing the crowding out literature, that this is possible, though not necessary: “public spiritedness and financial reward [might not be] mutually exclusive, at least up to a point.” Moreover, changing the mix of individuals “could be a good,” given the failures of the current crop of people.
    The same arguments can be applied to performance-based compensation for prison providers. I would add that, to the extent we’re considering performance-based compensation for private firms rather than public servants, we don’t need to worry about making providers any more mercenary than they already are: if there’s one thing advocates and opponents of private prisons agree on, it’s that private prison providers are a profit-oriented bunch. Not that the profit motive is inconsistent with public-interestedness: public servants “profit” from their employment too without being accused of thereby necessarily becoming mercenaries; moreover, corrections professionals move between the public and private sectors and presumably take their professionalism with them. Finally, as I discuss further below, performance-based compensation, combined with social impact bonds, allows nonprofits to raise money from private investors, so to this extent, introducing the profit motive may turn out to be a great boon for charitable and public-interested providers.
    2. Risk and Capital Requirements
    a. The Risk Is in the Slope
    We’ve seen, in the discussion of Charles Logan’s approach above, the concern that performance measures be based on factors that the relevant actor can actually control. Such concerns crop up frequently; James Q. Wilson even says, in the context of police departments, that public order and safety aren’t “‘real’ measures of overall success” because whatever about them is measurable “can only partially, if at all, be affected by police behavior.” When he does favor a “micro-level measure of success” of whether the neighborhood is becoming safer and more orderly, he still limits it to cases where the level of danger and disorder is “amenable . . . to improvement by a given, feasible level of police and public action.” The concern in the literature over controlling for baselines is similarly motivated.
    This seems mistaken: overall public order and safety are measures of the success of police departments, and (given that prison programs and conditions affect recidivism to some extent) lower recidivism is a measure of the success of prisons. It’s true that these measures come with a lot of noise attached—that is, with a lot of omitted variables reflecting the contribution of other people’s efforts, as well as environmental variables. But that doesn’t mean it’s wrong to use them for purposes of accountability, or even to tie compensation to them.
    There are two concerns about using these noisy measures: first, that the level of the unobserved variables at the beginning of the contract might establish a high-recidivism baseline, for which the contractor will have to be compensated very highly, or a low-recidivism baseline, for which the contractor will collect more than it deserves; and second, that variation in the unobserved variables might create a lot of risk for the contractor.
    As to the first concern, recall the earlier discussion about whether to control for baselines. Whether or not we adjust the contract price to take into account the baseline expected level of performance should have little effect on government expenditures: a high baseline translates into less quality being attributed to the contractor and thus to lower payments, and so the contractor will demand more money at the bidding stage, and vice versa.
    The same reasoning addresses the second concern: because controlling for baselines doesn’t affect the contractor’s payout—it basically amounts to adding or subtracting a constant, which is subtracted or added right back at the bidding stage—it also doesn’t necessarily affect risk.
    What definitely affects risk is not the level of compensation, but its slope. A contract that compensates the contractor based on the portion of performance he was able to control isn’t necessarily less risky than one that doesn’t, but a contract where the per-quality-unit price is lower is less risky. Thus, in the numerical example discussed earlier, a contract with a $1 reward per quality unit (regardless of the fixed component of the contract) is riskier than a contract with a $0.50 reward per quality unit; an even less risky contract is one with a $0 reward per quality unit, that is, a fixed-price contract, which is close to the norm; and the least risky possible contract is the cost-plus contract typical of rate-of-return regulation. Compensation based on a continuous quality measure is less risky than compensation based on a discrete quality measure (as long as the provider has some chance of being on either side of the cutoff); thus, “$1 for each quality unit” is less risky than “$5 but only if you get five quality units.”
    Do we care? Perhaps large corporations like CCA or The GEO Group, which are publicly traded and diversified across many contracts, can handle the risk; and they cover three-quarters of the industry. Smaller, privately held companies like MTC may be more sensitive to risk. Various potential entrants, especially nonprofits, must be even more sensitive. Adopting high-powered (i.e., high-slope) contracts may scare away the most risk-sensitive potential bidders, leaving the field to a few large corporations. (And it isn’t just a matter of risk: if the fixed part of the contract is paid up front while the reward is paid later, possibly a few years later once recidivism statistics come in, this might disadvantage small companies or nonprofits with limited access to capital markets.) This has potential implications for the competitiveness of the industry, possibilities for innovation, and the political influence that drives changes in criminal law.
    But the contract doesn’t have to be especially high-stakes. The optimal level of risk transfer is probably less than 100%. Rewarding the contractor for increases in quality with a price equal to the social value of quality gives the contractor great incentives but also (since the per-unit reward will be high) subjects him to high risk. Flat-fee contracts are relatively low risk but also low incentive. Some moderate level of risk transfer will optimally balance incentives with risk. Thus, the incentive-based portion of the contract is only 10% of the contract price in U.K.’s Doncaster prison, and was only 5% in the Federal Bureau of Prisons’ Taft demonstration project. Recall that in Britain’s Job Deal program, 30% of the payment is conditional, and only a third of that is related to “hard outcomes,” and even some of those outcomes are slightly “soft.”
    For the cash-flow issue noted above, one can also “change the timing of payments to providers,” for instance by making “a payment every six months for each offender who has not been reconvicted.”
    b. Financing Nonprofits: Social Impact Bonds
    The need to encourage the nonprofit sector calls for innovative funding mechanisms. Nonprofit prisons have been suggested though never implemented. But in light of the widespread concern that private prison firms will cut quality to save money, the nonprofit form seems like an obvious alternative.
    Ed Glaeser and Andrei Shleifer discuss the value of nonprofit status: by weakening the provider’s incentives to maximize profits, nonprofit status can be a valuable signal of quality when quality itself is nonverifiable. (Even using performance measures, it’s reasonable to suppose that some aspects of quality will remain nonverifiable; the value of nonprofit status depends on how important these remaining nonverifiable components are.) Moreover, altruistic entrepreneurs will tend to be attracted to the nonprofit form.
    And Timothy Besley and Maitreesh Ghatak show that, when both a provider and the government can make productive investments in a project, and when the provider is altruistic, then the provider should own the project if it values it more than the government does. Privatization can thus be more beneficial in the presence of altruistic providers.
    But banks or private equity houses are unlikely to finance such nonprofits, especially when the nonprofits don’t have much of a track record.
    Social impact bonds have been proposed as a funding mechanism for nonprofits. Rather than contracting directly with a provider, the government contracts with a middleman. This middleman, a “social impact bond-issuing organization,” has two functions. First, it hires the staff to provide the service. Second, it sells bonds to investors, particularly philanthropic ones; these bonds are essentially claims to a portion of the performance-based compensation. If the service provider fulfills the performance-based goals and receives its reward from the government, the investors make money; otherwise they don’t. At the Peterborough prison in the U.K., the government doesn’t pay anything unless recidivism is 7.5% less than in a comparison group, and payments are capped when the difference reaches 13%. The provider’s employees may well be paid something like a flat wage, so their monetary incentives aren’t great; but the bond-issuing organization and the philanthropic investors (whose money is on the line) are probably better at monitoring the staff than the government would be. It remains to be seen, though, whether the philanthropic sector will provide enough funds for nonprofit prison providers to be a viable alternative to for-profit corporations.
    In tomorrow’s post, I’ll finish up, after discussing how performance measures might lead to undesirable strategic behavior.

    N. Texas man sent to nursing home pushes to leave

    N. Texas man sent to nursing home pushes to leave

    Posted: Feb 27, 2014 6:12 PM CST Updated: Feb 27, 2014 6:12 PM CST
     


    An 85-year-old North Texas man said he couldn't get out of a local hospital on Wednesday. Instead of going home, he ended up in a nursing home.
    Charlie Fink called FOX 4 for help Wednesday after he went into Richardson Methodist Hospital on Friday for hernia surgery and wasn't released.
    Thursday, Fink was in an Arlington nursing home.
    "I tried to get out of Methodist and they locked the door," said Fink. "They wouldn't even let me out."
    While Fink was in the hospital, he was placed in the psychiatric unit, and the state was in court asking a Dallas County probate judge to find Fink unable to take care of himself.
    In an email, the state wrote, "APS was in court yesterday concerning the well-being of Mr. Fink. APS presented the information obtained by field staff to the court. Mr. Fink did have representation present at the hearing. An Emergency Order of Protection was presented in court. A judge did make a ruling on information presented. Due to confidentiality and to protect our client, that is all the information I can release."
    Fink's attorney said the state presented an anonymous referral, a doctor's affidavit to his health, concerns about his protecting himself and said that Fink had threatened case workers.
    Fink's wife, Edith, was removed from their home by APS earlier this month.
    Now the two, married 57 years, are together again – though, not in the place Fink wants to be because state law allows for the elderly to be removed from their home to protect them from themselves and others.
    "I just don't think they should have a law like that," said Fink. "I don't know who initiated this law. I don't know how old it is, but it should not be allowed to be."      


    Read more: http://www.myfoxdfw.com/story/24845464/elderly-man-state-sent-to-nursing-home-defends-independence#ixzz2ucRg1vyk

    Relatives of Sherman Hemsley contesting estate again

    Relatives of Sherman Hemsley contesting estate again

    By Aaron Bracamontes / El Paso Times
    Posted:   02/13/2014 08:15:56 PM MST


    More than a year after actor Sherman Hemsley was buried, the fight over his estate and remains continues.
    Now, the Eighth Court of Appeals, which had a hearing the matter Thursday, will have the final say on who gets Hemsley's estate.
    Richard and Robert Thornton, Hemsley's family members, are appealing a 2012 decision that upheld the will of Hemsley and gave his estate to his friend and business partner Flora Isela Enchinton Bernal. As part oof the appeal, lawyers for both sides gave oral arguments on Thursday.
    The Eighth Court of Appeals justices will take both arguments into consideration. A ruling could take several weeks or months.
    Hemsley, famous for his portrayal of George Jefferson in the sitcom "The Jeffersons," died from lung cancer in July 2012.
    His funeral was delayed until November because Richard Thornton, his biological half- brother from Philadelphia, took Enchinton to court over the estate and the right to bury him.
    Judge Patricia Chew ruled in 2012 that Enchinton was the proper beneficiary.
    On Thursday, the Thornton's lawyer, James D. Lucas, said it was "disturbing" that Enchinton, not Hemsley, called Julian Horwitz, the lawyer who drew up the will, to write up the will.
    According to testimony in the probate hearings, Enchinton called Horwitz and then Horwitz met Hemsley and read him the will in the hospital.
    "The way the will was executed should raise some concern," Lucas said in court. "Mr. Hemsley wanted to do it very fast. So was it read to him in three minutes, five minutes or more? He didn't know what was in the will."
    But Francisco Ortega, lawyer for Enchinton, countered by saying five witnesses testified that Hemsley insisted that Enchinton receive everything.
    "He repeatedly stated that he wanted Mrs. (Enchinton) Bernal to handle everything," Ortega said.
    Lucas also argued that even if Enchinton was the beneficiary, that the Health Code states that Thornton should have decided where he was buried because they are related.
    But Ortega said that code is "moot" since Hemsley has been buried at Fort Bliss National Cemetery and to dig him up would be disrespectful.
    Aaron Bracamontes may be reached at 546-6156.


    Thursday, February 27, 2014

    Ex-Chicago State worker wins whistleblower lawsuit

    Editor's note: Whistleblowers needed for the Probate Court of Cook County!  Lucius Verenus, Schoolmaster, ProbateSharks.com

     

    Ex-Chicago State worker wins whistleblower lawsuit

    Former senior counsel said he was fired after reporting alleged misconduct by university president, officials

     
    James Crowley
    James Crowley, former senior legal counsel for Chicago State University, was fired in February 2010. He said in a lawsuit that his termination was out of retaliation for reporting misconduct. (Terrence Antonio James, Chicago Tribune)
    A Cook County jury has awarded a former Chicago State University employee $2.5 million in damages and back pay after deciding he was fired in retaliation for reporting alleged misconduct by the university president and other top officials. A judge could further increase that amount at a hearing next month.
    It may be the first verdict stemming from a whistleblower claim filed under the state's ethics act, a 2003 law that laid out guidelines for behavior by state employees, according to the Illinois attorney general's office. That law includes whistleblower protection for employees who disclose activities they believe violate the ethics act.
    "We're not aware of another judgment like this," Attorney General spokeswoman Natalie Bauer said.
    The lawsuit by former Chicago State senior legal counsel James Crowley alleged that he was fired in February 2010 after he refused to withhold documents about university President Wayne Watson's employment that a faculty member requested under the state's public records law. Crowley also claimed that he was retaliated against after reporting questionable contracts to the attorney general's office.
    A university attorney argued in court that Crowley was fired for misusing university resources, including reserved parking spaces, and for giving preferential treatment in awarding a scholarship and paying for conference travel for a student.
    But a jury last week agreed with Crowley's version of events and awarded him $2 million in punitive damages and $480,000 in back pay for the last four years. It also ordered that he be reinstated to his job. Cook County Circuit Judge James McCarthy is scheduled to rule March 11 whether to double the amount of back pay and require the university to pay interest, both of which are included as remedies under the ethics law. McCarthy also is expected to decide whether Chicago State should pay Crowley's attorney fees.
    Crowley's lawsuit was against the university, a public institution on the city's South Side with 5,700 students; its president, Watson; and the seven trustees who were on the university board in 2010. The trial, which included testimony from Watson, lasted two weeks. A 14-member jury deliberated for less than an hour before delivering the verdict Feb. 18.
    "I'm very grateful to be free of the false allegations made against me by the Watson administration, and that have negatively affected my career for the past four years," Crowley wrote in a statement to the Tribune. "Hopefully, this prevents them from treating other employees as badly as they've treated me.
    "I also hope my case encourages not only employees of Chicago State, but all state employees, to report any wrongdoing to the proper state agency and know that they are protected."
    Chicago State said it will appeal. An insurance policy will cover the university's damages, school spokesman Thomas Wogan said.
    "The University stands behind our decision to defend this case in court. While we disagree with the decision of the jury, we fully respect the judicial process and we will pursue an appeal to their decision," Wogan said in a statement.
    Bauer said the attorney general's office was "not aware of another verdict like this under the whistleblower protection provision of the ethics act."
    The State Officials and Employees Ethics Act, enacted in 2003 by then-Gov. Rod Blagojevich, included a series of ethics overhauls designed to prevent and root out wrongdoing by public officials across the state. It is why state employees are now required to do annual ethics training, and why there is a state executive inspector general charged with investigating alleged corruption.
    The law also established civil and criminal penalties for those who violate the ethics act, and it included whistleblower protections for state workers who report misconduct.
    "The goal of the whole system was to encourage people to speak out when they see something wrong," said David Morrison, a policy adviser with the Illinois Campaign for Political Reform who helped draft the legislation. "If they suffer a harm when they are doing their job and raise a flag, they should be protected against retaliation."
    Morrison said the jury's decision to award more than $2 million in punitive damages sends a message that the law intended.
    "There is supposed to be a heavy hammer to discourage people from retaliating," Morrison said. "That is part of the cost of corruption that we will have to tally up. It is ultimately the taxpayers who lose, but it is the public official who should bear the fault for that. If they had run a clean ship, that would not have happened. It is up to the administration to set the right tone."
    Crowley, 47, a graduate of the DePaul University College of Law, began working at Chicago State in 2000. In August 2009, when Crowley's duties included answering requests for public records, he disagreed with Watson about how to respond to requests for information about Watson's employment and the presidential residence. Watson had recently been appointed Chicago State's president, but there was disagreement about whether he had begun to take over presidential responsibilities at that time.
    Watson's start date was a contentious issue because it determined whether he was eligible to begin drawing a pension based on his years as chancellor at City Colleges of Chicago. If he assumed the presidency Aug. 1 as originally outlined in his contract, he would have been ineligible for the pension because the law requires state university employees to wait 60 days after retiring from one job before taking another state job. His start date was later changed to Oct. 1.
    According to the lawsuit, in a meeting to discuss what documents to provide in response to the requests, Watson put his hand on Crowley's wrist and said to him: "If you read this my way, you are my friend; If you read it the other way, you are my enemy."

    Google ordered to remove anti-Islamic film from YouTube

    Google ordered to remove anti-Islamic film from YouTube

    • print
    • Email
      Share
      344
      LinkedIn
      1
    Visitors stand in front of a logo of YouTube at the YouTube Space Tokyo, operated by Google, in Tokyo
    Visitors stand in front of a logo of YouTube at the YouTube Space Tokyo, operated by Google, in Tokyo (Shohei Miyano Reuters, REUTERS / February 26, 2014)

    (Reuters) - A U.S. appeals court on Wednesday ordered Google Inc to remove from its YouTube video-sharing website an anti-Islamic film that had sparked protests across the Muslim world.

    By a 2-1 vote, a panel of the 9th U.S. Circuit Court of Appeals rejected Google's assertion that the removal of the film "Innocence of Muslims" amounted to a prior restraint of speech that violated the U.S. Constitution.

    The plaintiff, Cindy Lee Garcia, had objected to the film after learning that it incorporated a clip she had made for a different movie, which had been partially dubbed and in which she appeared to be asking: "Is your Mohammed a child molester?"

    In a statement, Google said: "We strongly disagree with this ruling and will fight it."

    Cris Armenta, a lawyer for Garcia, said she is delighted with the decision.

    "Ordering YouTube and Google to take down the film was the right thing to do," Armenta said in an email. "The propaganda film differs so radically from anything that Ms. Garcia could have imagined when the director told her that she was being cast in the innocent adventure film."

    The controversial film, billed as a film trailer, depicted the Prophet Mohammed as a fool and a sexual deviant. It sparked a torrent of anti-American unrest among Muslims in Egypt, Libya and other countries in 2012.

    That outbreak coincided with an attack on U.S. diplomatic facilities in Benghazi that killed four Americans, including the U.S. ambassador to Libya. U.S. and other foreign embassies were also stormed in the Middle East, Asia and Africa.

    For many Muslims, any depiction of the prophet is considered blasphemous.

    Google had refused to remove the film from YouTube, despite pressure from the White House and others, though it blocked the trailer in Egypt, Libya and certain other countries.

    In court filings, Google argued that Garcia appeared in the film for five seconds, and that while she might have legal claims against the director, she should not win a copyright lawsuit against Google.

    The film has now become an important part of public debate, Google argued, and should not be taken down.

    "Our laws permit even the vilest criticisms of governments, political leaders, and religious figures as legitimate exercises in free speech," the company wrote.

    But Garcia argued that her performance within the film was independently copyrightable and that she retained an interest in that copyright.

    A lower court had refused her request that Google remove the film from YouTube. In Wednesday's decision, however, 9th Circuit Chief Judge Alex Kozinski said Garcia was likely to prevail on her copyright claim, and having already faced "serious threats against her life," faced irreparable harm absent an injunction.

    He called it a rare and troubling case, given how Garcia had been duped. "It's disappointing, though perhaps not surprising, that Garcia needed to sue in order to protect herself and her rights," he wrote.

    The case is Garcia vs. Google Inc et al., 9th U.S. Circuit Court of Appeals, No. 12-57302.

    (Reporting by Jonathan Stempel in New York and Dan Levine in San Francisco; editing by David Gregorio, G Crosse and Dan Grebler)